The federalist

Can America Become Postliberal?

Regime ‌change begins at ​home, and ⁣we ⁢need ‍it. Our nation has been​ run into the⁤ ground, ‌and our ⁢leaders seems ‍at⁣ best clueless about, and at⁢ worst​ complicit ⁢in, the destruction.‌ But‌ replacing an elite caste is difficult; ⁣elites are, well,​ elite ​in‌ power and⁤ connections,⁢ even if ‍not in competence.

‌ ⁢

Notre Dame political theory professor Patrick Deneen has some‌ ideas about ⁤why our elites are so ‌bad, and ⁣what to do about it.⁣ A ⁤half-decade after his ‌successful ⁢book Why Liberalism Failed,‌ Deneen is ready⁤ to answer​ the question,⁤ “What⁤ now?” with Regime Change: ‍Toward⁣ a Postliberal ⁤Future. He⁤ deserves​ credit for attempting to⁣ build and ⁢not just⁣ critique,⁢ and⁣ this volume is⁢ an insightful, challenging, and sometimes perplexing sketch of what ⁣has⁤ gone wrong‌ in ⁣our ⁣nation, and what ⁣might be done ‍to put⁤ it right.

The book’s diagnosis begins​ with ‌a critique of liberalism that emphasizes​ how the persistent divide between the few and​ the many ⁢is ⁤exacerbated by liberalism, which suppresses the⁣ views ⁢of the many in ⁤the name of progress. Some sort ⁤of ⁢elite is inevitable, ⁣but⁢ liberalism⁤ encourages an ⁣elite‍ that is antithetical to the many.

Deneen argues that an ideological commitment to​ progress⁤ will always be ‌directed against ‍the people, who naturally tend to⁤ be⁢ conservative. What ‌the ​people need and want “is stability, ‍order, continuity ‍and⁤ a sense‍ of⁢ gratitude for the past‍ and obligation toward ‌the future,” ⁣which is to⁣ say,⁢ a “conservatism ⁢that⁢ conserves.” What liberalism⁣ offers ⁢in​ its classical form is the ⁣churning, ​dislocating “creative destruction” ⁢of the global marketplace and, in‍ its progressive ⁢form, ⁢the dissolving ​moral ⁢and social chaos of revolution against old norms, obligations, and communities. And the two varieties are⁢ increasingly ​combined ‌in woke⁤ capitalism.

‘Aristopopulism’

‌ ​

Elite ‌obsessions with race, sex, ⁣and so-called⁤ gender‌ allow them​ to wage culture war as‍ class war against the working class. Even as they enjoy the ‌prestige ​and​ material rewards of their status,⁢ our elites wallow ⁢in‍ claims of⁤ victimization and justify their⁢ assaults on ⁤the lower⁢ classes by ludicrously designating ‌them ​as oppressors who‌ deserve their ⁣lot. Hence the spectacle of‍ some⁢ of the most privileged people in history claiming that ‍disagreement with, say, gender ideology, ‌is an⁢ active form of harm‍ that threatens ​their ⁣safety⁣ and ⁤must therefore⁢ be suppressed ​and excluded. Somehow, ‍the ⁣ostensibly marginalized and oppressed⁤ have every major corporation lining up to ⁢sponsor them ​and squash their enemies.

Our​ leadership class is rotten,‌ but Deneen’s castigation of the elites does⁢ not let poor and working-class Americans ⁣off the hook;⁣ they⁢ have​ too often joined in the destruction of ⁤their families​ and communities. And reaction against the⁢ elites‌ is not enough to revive ⁢the remains of ⁤a healthy working-class culture. In​ Deneen’s ‍view, the populist ‍revolt ‍against the elites has ⁤thus ⁣far⁣ been “untutored ⁤and ill ⁢led”​ with ​former President Trump a‌ “deeply flawed narcissist” who failed to ⁣deliver‌ on ‌too many ⁣promises.‌ Tanking ⁤Bud Light and ‍Target ‍is satisfying but not nearly enough.

Thus, ‌Deneen calls for renewal in the form ⁢of a​ mixed regime that goes beyond‌ balancing the⁣ interests of the‌ elites ​and ‌the‌ masses against each other, ⁤and instead seeks ​to⁤ create‍ genuine solidarity ​between them.⁣ Though‌ the⁢ U.S. ⁢has ​never had an ‌aristocracy as ⁣such, ​Deneen identifies ‍the ⁤professional classes ‍— such​ as​ doctors, clergy, and⁣ lawyers⁤ — as ⁣having‍ long served some of ‌the same​ conservative⁤ aristocratic imperatives‍ to “resist the⁢ innovators and ⁤elevate the masses.” Local leaders ⁢tend ⁤to ⁤be more⁣ dedicated to the good of their communities, ⁢including the working poor, ​than far-away ⁣moneymen and social justice​ schemers.

Establishing the sort of ⁣“aristopopulism” Deneen envisions will require a ⁣combination of populist pressure‍ and class traitors. The end goal ‌is ⁢to change the elites, ‌in ⁣part ⁤by replacing them, ⁣and in part by providing ⁢new incentives that require⁣ them to serve the ⁤common good in‌ order to‍ keep their ​power⁤ and positions.‌ Deneen hopes ‍for ⁣a cadre ⁢of elites who will⁢ harness populist ‌political ⁤energy to establish themselves as​ a vanguard⁤ of the‍ common good,⁢ and Ohio⁣ Sen. J.D. Vance, who has⁣ promoted Regime Change,⁤ may⁢ be ⁢a prototype.

Deneen offers a variety ‌of proposals ‍that⁤ Vance ⁣and⁢ others might ⁤pursue. ⁣For example, regarding the use of corporate power‍ to ‍impose economic sanctions on ‌socially conservative ⁣states, he⁢ writes, “Any economic ​institution with sufficient⁤ power to bring financial ruin ⁤upon a sovereign political entity should⁢ be severely curtailed in⁣ the name​ of the ⁤common good.” ‌This insistence⁢ that the market be ​subordinated‍ to non-economic considerations may be heresy to some on the‌ right, but it is a​ necessary corrective.

⁤ ‌

Deneen ⁢is ⁤likewise right⁤ that liberalism’s⁤ claim to⁣ neutrality ⁢is a lie. It ​is impossible to really‌ be​ neutral ⁣between ‌good‍ and evil, ‍God⁢ and ‌Satan, ‍truth ⁣and falsehood.⁣ There⁤ is nothing neutral, for ‌example, about‌ liberalism’s embrace of the ⁤idea of⁣ rational adult⁢ individuals as politically normative, and‌ this ahistorical understanding​ of⁢ human persons ⁣has ‌a host of ill‍ effects, ‍led ‍by‌ the disdain it inculcates for ‌dependence. As ​Deneen notes, “Every political order ‍rests on certain ⁤theological⁣ assumptions,” and ⁤he is skilled ⁤at unmasking those​ upon⁢ which the varieties of ⁤liberalism are⁢ based.

Deneen does⁢ briefly note the Christian ‍roots ⁣of liberalism, and it ⁤would have been illuminating⁢ had he engaged seriously​ with⁣ David⁣ Walsh (another former professor ​of mine) who has made ⁣perhaps‍ the ‍most⁣ compelling case ⁢for ⁣liberalism on these‍ grounds.⁤ However, we cannot ⁢ask for everything of‍ interest to be included‌ in one book.‍ We ‌may also⁢ forgive some generalizations ​and imprecision in a political⁤ theory ⁢book for⁤ a general audience.

Nonetheless, even a‍ sympathetic⁢ reader must⁤ wrestle with ⁢aspects of Deneen’s arguments. It⁣ is not just that ​he leaves tensions unresolved, but that he ignores some of them, ⁣thereby ⁤leaving some‌ of ‍his⁢ views ⁤opaque. An ‌obvious ⁤example is that his‍ emphasis on the few and ​the many elides the importance of the ‍middle class in the United ‍States. ⁤The country ‌is filled with those who are⁢ neither ‌working⁣ class⁤ nor elite, and have both benefited from and been harmed​ by liberalism.⁣ Yet⁤ Deneen seems to shy⁤ away ‍from analyzing ⁢this class, even though ⁤their loyalties‍ can make ⁣or break his‍ political and⁤ cultural project.

⁤ ⁢ Restoration‌ or‍ Subversion?

⁣ ‍

More ⁤fundamental still ⁣is the question of ⁣whether Deneen’s vision of regime change is conservative. Is ⁤his goal to “restore ‌the republic” ‌or to replace it by​ quietly subverting​ it ⁤into a functionally​ different regime? ‌This in turn is bound ⁢up ⁤with⁣ the ‍question of ⁣whether⁢ the ⁣United States was founded as a fundamentally liberal nation — if so, does American ⁢conservatism necessarily consist of‌ merely preserving ​an earlier iteration ​of liberalism?

Many on ‍the right have answered yes, arguing that American conservatism ⁤is‌ dedicated ⁢to ​the preservation and​ perfection of the classical liberalism famously ⁣expressed in the preamble‌ to⁤ the⁣ Declaration ‍of Independence. ⁣This interpretation of American conservatism is⁤ fundamentally ‍revolutionary ⁢and ⁢ultimately oppressive, but it has been ‍widely championed by ⁤a⁣ host of self-described⁣ conservatives, led by disciples ⁣of the Claremont professor and Lincoln⁢ biographer Harry Jaffa.

The prominence⁤ of this ideology‌ prompts Deneen to⁣ denounce ⁣“what has passed for ‘conservatism’‍ in‌ the​ United States for the ⁣past half century” as ⁢simply ⁢another variety ⁣of liberalism. In contrast, he⁣ champions an older tradition ⁤that American conservatives can look to, ⁤and describes the postliberal new right as “a rediscovery of⁣ early-modern forms⁤ of conservatism” and its thinkers, ⁢who “warned of the⁣ dangers emerging ‍from an ideology of progress.” Among​ the examples he cites are the ⁣American colonists (as seen in the actual text of​ Winthrop’s⁢ oft-quoted “city set on a hill”​ sermon) ⁢and⁤ the‌ anti-federalists.

Indeed, Deneen could have written much more about our nation’s non-liberal heritage and ⁢how ⁢conservatives may learn⁢ from it. Unfortunately, his‌ appreciation for our ⁤conservative‍ patrimony and his judgment of‍ the Constitution⁣ and the founding seems to ‍remain ambiguous, ​if not ⁣hostile. ‍For example, he refers to‌ the ‍“progressive‌ liberalism of⁤ America’s Founding​ Fathers” and asserts that⁤ “the American⁣ constitutional‍ order …⁤ represented‍ the Founder’s‍ belief in …⁣ a system ⁣in which a designated ‌elite‌ would⁤ govern ‍with ⁤an aim to advancing‍ an ⁣ideal of progress‍ while rendering⁣ tractable any recalcitrant popular ​resistance.”

​ ⁣

Thus, the ‍question⁤ remains of whether ⁢Deneen believes that ⁢genuine American conservatism ‌is compatible with our‍ Constitution, ‍and therefore ‌whether his vision of ‌regime⁤ change is ​conservative. ‍Deneen ‌seems, ‍at best, ambivalent, arguing ​for the “peaceful⁤ but vigorous overthrow of our corrupt and‍ corrupting liberal ​ruling class and‍ the creation of a⁤ postliberal order in‍ which ⁢existing‍ political forms ​can remain​ in place, ‍as long as ⁤a fundamentally different ethos ‌informs those ‌institutions and the personnel who populate​ key offices ⁢and ⁣positions.”

Deneen’s​ sufferance of⁤ our Constitutional system​ appears conditional ⁤on‌ it being‌ run by a new elite with an​ ethos contrary ⁢not only‌ to that​ of our​ current leaderships ⁤class, ⁤but also‍ to that of⁢ our‍ founders. However, we​ may‍ wonder why this new​ elite, ⁢if‍ they acquired the power Deneen⁣ hopes‌ for, ‍would ⁣not ⁣try to change our ‌political forms to something ‍not‍ founded on liberalism. Would anything other than the difficulty of formally amending our supreme‌ law‍ restrain them?

⁢ ⁢

Consequently, though Deneen says he wants to use Machiavellian ‌means to Aristotelian ends,‌ it ​is ‍possible to read⁢ him as‌ urging something more like⁤ Platonic‍ means for ⁤Platonic‌ ends — encouraging his‌ readers to imagine themselves as philosopher-kings⁤ seizing ⁢control of ⁣and rerouting ⁣the ship of state. He is, ⁢after all,​ writing for​ the‍ new elite, and ‌it ⁤is, ​at ⁣best, unclear whether ⁢they⁤ should⁢ be ​restorationist or ⁢subversive⁣ of ‌our⁤ constitutional order.

Deneen’s ‍ambiguity on⁣ this ‌separates‍ him ‌from‌ the many conservatives who,⁣ despite generally​ agreeing with his⁣ critique⁣ of​ liberalism, do not ⁤believe​ our nation’s founding was irredeemably ⁢liberal. This might⁢ also explain⁢ Deneen’s inaccurate attack on‍ Ryan Anderson and‌ Robert‍ George — they⁢ certainly‌ do ‍not ​believe that the good “must be a matter of ‍private or subpolitical ⁢civic concern,” ​but they are​ advocates ⁢for ⁣our‌ constitutional‍ order.

And they ⁤should be.⁤ The founders were not liberal⁣ ideologues, ‌but statesmen whose ideas​ were ⁣a sort of political and cultural syncretism. As⁤ I have put it, “Our nation’s heritage‍ and founding ‌principles …‍ deliberately tempered ⁤and restrained liberal ​ideology. ​Locke was⁢ in ⁣the air at ‍the ⁤time, but⁢ so were ⁤Lycurgus and Leviticus. The American system ⁣of government was devised ‌not from ideological⁢ abstractions,‍ but ​from experience and compromise.” Despite Jefferson’s Lockean‍ flourishes, ⁣the American founding⁣ was imbued with many​ non-liberal elements.

Therefore,⁢ there is⁤ tension in ‍Deneen’s conclusion.⁤ He urges that we‌ learn‌ from the⁢ “common-good conservative tradition”⁤ yet seems unwilling to acknowledge​ its‍ role in ‍our founding and ‍Constitution. And so his closing ⁢call to “abandon the ruins‌ we have ‍made ‌…⁢ and then⁤ build ⁢anew” may ‍be ​read ‌as either conservative or‌ radical — ‍not to mention ‍unclear. ‍Does⁢ Deneen want us​ to rebuild and ⁢renew our ancestral political and cultural ​order,‍ or ‍to create a‍ new order⁣ for the ages ​amid the⁢ wreck ⁣of‍ liberalism?

​ ‌ ​ ‌


Read More From Original Article Here: Is A Postliberal America Even Possible?

" Conservative News Daily does not always share or support the views and opinions expressed here; they are just those of the writer."
*As an Amazon Associate I earn from qualifying purchases

Related Articles

Sponsored Content
Back to top button
Available for Amazon Prime
Close

Adblock Detected

Please consider supporting us by disabling your ad blocker